Arthur Danto  

From The Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia

(Difference between revisions)
Jump to: navigation, search
Revision as of 23:01, 6 May 2009
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)
(Arthur Danto moved to Arthur Coleman Danto)
← Previous diff
Revision as of 11:42, 28 October 2013
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

Next diff →
Line 1: Line 1:
-{{Template}}'''Arthur Coleman Danto''' (b. [[1924]]) is an [[United States|American]] [[art critic]], and [[professor]] of [[philosophy]] who came to prominence with his [[1964]] essay on "[[the end of art]]" after [[Warhol]]'s [[Brillo Box]]es exposition. +{{Template}}
 + 
 +'''Arthur Coleman Danto''' (January 1, 1924 – October 25, 2013) was an [[American art critic]] and philosopher. Danto came to prominence with his [[1964]] essay "[[The Artworld]]," which argued "[[the end of art]]" after [[Andy Warhol]]'s [[Brillo Box]]es exposition.
== Biography == == Biography ==
He was born in [[Ann Arbor]], [[Michigan]], in 1924, and grew up in [[Detroit]]. After spending two years in the Army, Danto studied art and history at Wayne University (now [[Wayne State University]]) and then pursued graduate study in philosophy at [[Columbia University]]. From 1949 to 1950, Danto studied in [[Paris]] on a [[Fulbright]] scholarship under [[Maurice Merleau-Ponty]], and in 1951 returned to teach at Columbia, where he is currently Johnsonian Professor of Philosophy Emeritus. He was born in [[Ann Arbor]], [[Michigan]], in 1924, and grew up in [[Detroit]]. After spending two years in the Army, Danto studied art and history at Wayne University (now [[Wayne State University]]) and then pursued graduate study in philosophy at [[Columbia University]]. From 1949 to 1950, Danto studied in [[Paris]] on a [[Fulbright]] scholarship under [[Maurice Merleau-Ponty]], and in 1951 returned to teach at Columbia, where he is currently Johnsonian Professor of Philosophy Emeritus.
-He is best known for his work in philosophical [[aesthetics]] and [[philosophy of history]], though he has contributed significantly to a number of fields, His interests span thought, feeling, [[philosophy of art]], theories of [[Representation (arts)|representation]], [[Theoretical psychology|philosophical psychology]], [[Hegel]]'s [[aesthetics]], and the philosophers [[Merleau-Ponty|Maurice Merleau-Ponty]] and [[Schopenhauer|Arthur Schopenhauer]].+He is best known for his work in philosophical [[aesthetics]] and [[philosophy of history]], though he has contributed significantly to a number of fields, His interests span thought, feeling, [[philosophy of art]], theories of [[Representation (arts)|representation]], [[Theoretical psychology|philosophical psychology]], [[Hegel's aesthetics]], and the philosophers [[Merleau-Ponty|Maurice Merleau-Ponty]] and [[Schopenhauer|Arthur Schopenhauer]].
-In [[art criticism]], his publications include the collections ''Encounters and Reflections: Art in the Historical Present'' (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1990), which won the [[National Book Critics Circle]] Prize for Criticism in 1990; ''Beyond the Brillo Box: The Visual Arts in Post-Historical Perspective'' (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1992); ''Playing With the Edge: The Photographic Achievement of [[Robert Mapplethorpe]]'' (University of California, 1995); and ''The Madonna of the Future: Essays in a Pluralistic Art World'' (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 2000) and ''Unnatural Wonders: Essays from the Gap Between Art and Life''.+In [[art criticism]], his publications include the collections ''Encounters and Reflections: Art in the Historical Present'' (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1990), which won the [[National Book Critics Circle]] Prize for Criticism in 1990; ''Beyond the Brillo Box: The Visual Arts in Post-Historical Perspective'' (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1992); ''Playing With the Edge: The Photographic Achievement of [[Robert Mapplethorpe]]'' (University of California, 1995); and ''The Madonna of the Future: Essays in a Pluralistic Art World'' (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 2000) and ''[[Unnatural Wonders: Essays from the Gap Between Art and Life]]''.
A art critic for ''[[The Nation (U.S. periodical)|The Nation]]'', he has also published numerous articles in other journals. In addition, he is an editor of the ''[[Journal of Philosophy]]'' and a contributing editor of the ''[[Naked Punch Review]]'' and ''[[Artforum]]''. A art critic for ''[[The Nation (U.S. periodical)|The Nation]]'', he has also published numerous articles in other journals. In addition, he is an editor of the ''[[Journal of Philosophy]]'' and a contributing editor of the ''[[Naked Punch Review]]'' and ''[[Artforum]]''.
Line 12: Line 14:
He has been the recipient of many fellowships and grants including two [[Guggenheim Fellowship]]s, [[American Council of Learned Societies|ACLS]], and [[Fulbright Program|Fulbright]], and has served as Vice-President and President of the [[American Philosophical Association]], as well as President of the American Society for [[Aesthetics]]. He has been the recipient of many fellowships and grants including two [[Guggenheim Fellowship]]s, [[American Council of Learned Societies|ACLS]], and [[Fulbright Program|Fulbright]], and has served as Vice-President and President of the [[American Philosophical Association]], as well as President of the American Society for [[Aesthetics]].
 +==Thought==
 +Danto is best known as the influential, long-time art critic for ''[[The Nation]]'' and for his work in philosophical [[aesthetics]] and [[philosophy of history]], though he has contributed significantly to a number of fields, including the [[philosophy of action]]. His interests included thought, feeling, [[philosophy of art]], theories of [[Representation (arts)|representation]], [[Theoretical psychology|philosophical psychology]], [[Hegel's aesthetics]], and the philosophers [[Friedrich Nietzsche]], and [[Arthur Schopenhauer]].
 +
 +==="Artworld" and the Definition of Art===
 +Danto laid the groundwork for an institutional definition of art that sought to answer the questions raised by the emerging phenomenon of twentieth century art. The definition of the term “art” is a subject of constant contention and many books and journal articles have been published arguing over the answer to the question, [[Aesthetics#What is .22art.3F.22|What is Art?]] Definitions can be categorized into conventional and non-conventional definitions. Non-conventional definitions take a concept like the aesthetic as an intrinsic characteristic in order to account for the phenomena of art. Conventional definitions reject this connection to aesthetic, formal, or expressive properties as essential to defining art but rather, in either an institutional or historical sense, say that “art” is basically a sociological category. In terms of [[classificatory disputes about art]], Danto takes a conventional approach. His "institutional definition of art" considers whatever art schools, museums, and artists get away with, regardless of formal definitions. Danto has written on this subject in several of his recent works and a detailed treatment is to be found in ''Transfiguration of the Commonplace''.
 +
 +The essay "[[The Artworld]]" in which Danto coined the term “artworld”, by which he meant cultural context or “an atmosphere of art theory,” first appeared in the ''Journal of Philosophy'' (1964) and has since been widely reprinted. It has had considerable influence on aesthetic philosophy and, according to professor of philosophy [[Stephen David Ross]], "especially upon [[George Dickie|George Dickie's]] [[institutional theory of art]]. Dickie defines an art work as an artifact 'which has had conferred upon it the status of candidate for appreciation by some person or persons acting in behalf of a certain social institution (the artworld)' (p. 43.)"
 +
 +According to the ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', "Danto's definition has been glossed as follows: something is a work of art if and only if (i) it has a subject (ii) about which it projects some attitude or point of view (has a style) (iii) by means of rhetorical ellipsis (usually metaphorical) which ellipsis engages audience participation in filling in what is missing, and (iv) where the work in question and the interpretations thereof require an art historical context. (Danto, Carroll) Clause (iv) is what makes the definition institutionalist. The view has been criticized for entailing that art criticism written in a highly rhetorical style is art, lacking but requiring an independent account of what makes a context art historical, and for not applying to music."
 +
 +===The End of Art===
 +The basic meaning of the term "art" has changed several times over the centuries, and has continued to evolve during the 20th century as well. Danto describes the history of Art in his own contemporary version of [[Hegel|Hegel's]] dialectical history of art. Danto claimed that a certain history of western art has come to an end. The "end of art" refers to the beginning of our modern era of art in which art no longer adheres to the constraints of [[mimesis|imitation theory]] but serves a new purpose. Art began with an "era of imitation, followed by an era of ideology, followed by our post-historical era in which, with qualification, anything goes... In our narrative, at first only mimesis [imitation] was art, then several things were art but each tried to extinguish its competitors, and then, finally, it became apparent that there were no stylistic or philosophical constraints. There is no special way works of art have to be. And that is the present and, I should say, the final moment in the master narrative. It is the end of the story."
 +
 +==Works==
 +===Books===
 +Danto is the author of numerous books on philosophy and art, including:
 +*''Nietzsche as Philosopher'' (1965)
 +*''Analytical Philosophy of Action'' (1973)
 +*''[[Jean-Paul Sartre]]'' (1975)
 +*''The Transfiguration of the Commonplace'' (1981)
 +*''Narration and Knowledge'' (1985) - Including earlier book ''Analytical Philosophy of History'' (1965)
 +*''Mysticism and Morality: Oriental Thought and Moral Philosophy'' (1987)
 +*''Connections to the World: The Basic Concepts of Philosophy'' (1997)
 +*''[[After the End of Art]]'' (1997)
 +*''The Abuse of Beauty'' (2003)
 +*''[[Red Grooms]]'' (2004)
 +*''[[Andy Warhol]]'' (2009)
 +
 +===Selected Essays===
 +*''The Artworld'' (1964)
 +*''The State of the Art'' (1987)
 +*''Encounters and Reflections: Art in the Historical Present'' (1990)
 +*''Beyond the Brillo Box: The Visual Arts in Post-Historical Perspective'' (1992)
 +*''Playing With the Edge: The Photographic Achievement of [[Robert Mapplethorpe]]'' (1995)
 +*''The Wake of Art: Criticism, Philosophy, and the Ends of Taste'' (1998)
 +*''[http://www.rae.com.pt/Danto%20hegel%20end%20art.pdf Hegel's End-of-Art Thesis]'' (1999)
 +*''[[The Madonna of the Future: Essays in a Pluralistic Art World]]'' (2000)
 +*''Philosophizing Art: Selected Essays'' (2001)
 +*''The Body/Body Problem: Selected Essays'' (2001)
 +*''The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art'' (2004)
 +*''[[Unnatural Wonders: Essays from the Gap Between Art and Life]]'' (2007)
{{GFDL}} {{GFDL}}

Revision as of 11:42, 28 October 2013

Related e

Wikipedia
Wiktionary
Shop


Featured:

Arthur Coleman Danto (January 1, 1924 – October 25, 2013) was an American art critic and philosopher. Danto came to prominence with his 1964 essay "The Artworld," which argued "the end of art" after Andy Warhol's Brillo Boxes exposition.

Contents

Biography

He was born in Ann Arbor, Michigan, in 1924, and grew up in Detroit. After spending two years in the Army, Danto studied art and history at Wayne University (now Wayne State University) and then pursued graduate study in philosophy at Columbia University. From 1949 to 1950, Danto studied in Paris on a Fulbright scholarship under Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and in 1951 returned to teach at Columbia, where he is currently Johnsonian Professor of Philosophy Emeritus.

He is best known for his work in philosophical aesthetics and philosophy of history, though he has contributed significantly to a number of fields, His interests span thought, feeling, philosophy of art, theories of representation, philosophical psychology, Hegel's aesthetics, and the philosophers Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Arthur Schopenhauer.

In art criticism, his publications include the collections Encounters and Reflections: Art in the Historical Present (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1990), which won the National Book Critics Circle Prize for Criticism in 1990; Beyond the Brillo Box: The Visual Arts in Post-Historical Perspective (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1992); Playing With the Edge: The Photographic Achievement of Robert Mapplethorpe (University of California, 1995); and The Madonna of the Future: Essays in a Pluralistic Art World (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 2000) and Unnatural Wonders: Essays from the Gap Between Art and Life.

A art critic for The Nation, he has also published numerous articles in other journals. In addition, he is an editor of the Journal of Philosophy and a contributing editor of the Naked Punch Review and Artforum.

Danto is also the author of numerous non-art books, including Nietzsche as Philosopher, Mysticism and Morality, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, Narration and Knowledge, Connections to the World: The Basic Concepts of Philosophy.

He has been the recipient of many fellowships and grants including two Guggenheim Fellowships, ACLS, and Fulbright, and has served as Vice-President and President of the American Philosophical Association, as well as President of the American Society for Aesthetics.

Thought

Danto is best known as the influential, long-time art critic for The Nation and for his work in philosophical aesthetics and philosophy of history, though he has contributed significantly to a number of fields, including the philosophy of action. His interests included thought, feeling, philosophy of art, theories of representation, philosophical psychology, Hegel's aesthetics, and the philosophers Friedrich Nietzsche, and Arthur Schopenhauer.

"Artworld" and the Definition of Art

Danto laid the groundwork for an institutional definition of art that sought to answer the questions raised by the emerging phenomenon of twentieth century art. The definition of the term “art” is a subject of constant contention and many books and journal articles have been published arguing over the answer to the question, What is Art? Definitions can be categorized into conventional and non-conventional definitions. Non-conventional definitions take a concept like the aesthetic as an intrinsic characteristic in order to account for the phenomena of art. Conventional definitions reject this connection to aesthetic, formal, or expressive properties as essential to defining art but rather, in either an institutional or historical sense, say that “art” is basically a sociological category. In terms of classificatory disputes about art, Danto takes a conventional approach. His "institutional definition of art" considers whatever art schools, museums, and artists get away with, regardless of formal definitions. Danto has written on this subject in several of his recent works and a detailed treatment is to be found in Transfiguration of the Commonplace.

The essay "The Artworld" in which Danto coined the term “artworld”, by which he meant cultural context or “an atmosphere of art theory,” first appeared in the Journal of Philosophy (1964) and has since been widely reprinted. It has had considerable influence on aesthetic philosophy and, according to professor of philosophy Stephen David Ross, "especially upon George Dickie's institutional theory of art. Dickie defines an art work as an artifact 'which has had conferred upon it the status of candidate for appreciation by some person or persons acting in behalf of a certain social institution (the artworld)' (p. 43.)"

According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, "Danto's definition has been glossed as follows: something is a work of art if and only if (i) it has a subject (ii) about which it projects some attitude or point of view (has a style) (iii) by means of rhetorical ellipsis (usually metaphorical) which ellipsis engages audience participation in filling in what is missing, and (iv) where the work in question and the interpretations thereof require an art historical context. (Danto, Carroll) Clause (iv) is what makes the definition institutionalist. The view has been criticized for entailing that art criticism written in a highly rhetorical style is art, lacking but requiring an independent account of what makes a context art historical, and for not applying to music."

The End of Art

The basic meaning of the term "art" has changed several times over the centuries, and has continued to evolve during the 20th century as well. Danto describes the history of Art in his own contemporary version of Hegel's dialectical history of art. Danto claimed that a certain history of western art has come to an end. The "end of art" refers to the beginning of our modern era of art in which art no longer adheres to the constraints of imitation theory but serves a new purpose. Art began with an "era of imitation, followed by an era of ideology, followed by our post-historical era in which, with qualification, anything goes... In our narrative, at first only mimesis [imitation] was art, then several things were art but each tried to extinguish its competitors, and then, finally, it became apparent that there were no stylistic or philosophical constraints. There is no special way works of art have to be. And that is the present and, I should say, the final moment in the master narrative. It is the end of the story."

Works

Books

Danto is the author of numerous books on philosophy and art, including:

  • Nietzsche as Philosopher (1965)
  • Analytical Philosophy of Action (1973)
  • Jean-Paul Sartre (1975)
  • The Transfiguration of the Commonplace (1981)
  • Narration and Knowledge (1985) - Including earlier book Analytical Philosophy of History (1965)
  • Mysticism and Morality: Oriental Thought and Moral Philosophy (1987)
  • Connections to the World: The Basic Concepts of Philosophy (1997)
  • After the End of Art (1997)
  • The Abuse of Beauty (2003)
  • Red Grooms (2004)
  • Andy Warhol (2009)

Selected Essays





Unless indicated otherwise, the text in this article is either based on Wikipedia article "Arthur Danto" or another language Wikipedia page thereof used under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License; or on research by Jahsonic and friends. See Art and Popular Culture's copyright notice.

Personal tools