Fellow of the British Academy  

From The Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia

(Difference between revisions)
Jump to: navigation, search
Revision as of 12:16, 14 March 2019
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

← Previous diff
Current revision
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

Line 1: Line 1:
-{{Template}}+#REDIRECT [[The British Academy]]
-'''Michael Joseph Oakeshott''' [[Fellow of the British Academy|FBA]] (11 December 1901 – 19 December 1990) was an [[English philosopher]] and [[political theory|political theorist]] who wrote about [[philosophy of history]], [[philosophy of religion]], [[aesthetics]], [[philosophy of education]], and [[philosophy of law]].+{{R from move}}
- +
-He is the author of "[[On Being Conservative]]".+
- +
-'''Michael Joseph Oakeshott''' [[Fellow of the British Academy|FBA]] ({{IPAc-en|ˈ|oʊ|k|ʃ|ɒ|t}}; 11 December 1901 – 19 December 1990) was an English [[philosopher]] and [[political theory|political theorist]] who wrote about [[philosophy of history]], [[philosophy of religion]], [[aesthetics]], [[philosophy of education]], and [[philosophy of law]].<ref name=political_theory_journal>Fuller, T. (1991) 'The Work of Michael Oakeshott', ''Political Theory'', Vol. 19 No. 3.</ref>+
- +
-== Biography ==+
- +
-===Early life===+
-Oakeshott was the son of Frances Maude (Hellicar) and Joseph Francis Oakeshott, a [[civil servant]] and a member of the [[Fabian Society]].<ref>http://www.aim25.ac.uk/cgi-bin/vcdf/detail?coll_id=8042&inst_id=1</ref> [[George Bernard Shaw]] was a friend. Michael Oakeshott attended [[St George's School, Harpenden]], from 1912 to 1920. He enjoyed his schooldays, and the Headmaster, Cecil Grant, later became a friend. {{citation needed|date=October 2011}}+
- +
-In 1920 Oakeshott became an undergraduate at [[Gonville and Caius College, Cambridge]], where he read history. He obtained an MA and subsequently became a Fellow. While he was at Cambridge he admired the [[British idealist]] philosophers [[J. M. E. McTaggart]] and [[John Grote]], and the medieval historian [[Zachary Nugent Brooke]]. The historian [[Herbert Butterfield]] was a contemporary and fellow member of the Junior Historians society.{{citation needed|date=October 2011}}+
- +
-===1930s===+
-Oakeshott was dismayed by the political extremism that occurred in Europe during the 1930s, and his surviving lectures from this period reveal a dislike of [[Nazism|National Socialism]] and [[Marxism]].<ref>See M. Oakeshott, Review of H. Levy and others, ''Aspects of Dialectical Materialism'', in ''Cambridge Review'', 56 (1934–5), pp. 108–9</ref>+
- +
-===Second World War===+
-Although Oakeshott, in his essay "The Claim of Politics" (1939), defended the right of individuals not to become directly involved, in 1941 he joined the [[British Army]]. He reportedly wished to join the [[Special Operations Executive]] (SOE), but the military decided that his appearance was "too unmistakably English" for him to conduct covert operations on the Continent.<ref>{{cite web|last1=Gray|first1=John|title=Last of the Idealists|url=http://www.literaryreview.co.uk/gray_07_14.php|website=Literary Review|accessdate=23 July 2014|deadurl=yes|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20140717092255/http://www.literaryreview.co.uk/gray_07_14.php|archivedate=17 July 2014|df=dmy-all}}</ref> He was on active service in Europe with the intelligence unit [[GHQ Liaison Regiment|Phantom]], which had connections with the [[Special Air Service]] (SAS), but he was never in the front line.+
- +
-===Postwar===+
-In 1945 Oakeshott was demobilized and returned to Cambridge. In 1947 he left Cambridge for [[Nuffield College, Oxford]], but after only a year there he secured an appointment as Professor of Political Science at the [[London School of Economics]] (LSE), succeeding the leftist [[Harold Laski]]. He was deeply unsympathetic to the student activism at LSE during the late 1960s, on the grounds that it disrupted the work of the university. Oakeshott retired from the LSE in 1969.+
- +
-In his retirement he retreated to live quietly in a country cottage in [[Langton Matravers]] in [[Dorset]] with his third wife. He was divorced twice and had numerous affairs, some of them with wives of his students and colleagues, and even with a girlfriend of his son Simon.<ref>Paul Franco, Leslie Marsh, ''A Companion to Michael Oakeshott'', pp. 31</ref> He also had an out-of-wedlock son Sebastian. His most famous lover was [[Iris Murdoch]].<ref>Paul Franco, ''Michael Oakeshott: An Introduction'', pp. 22</ref>+
- +
-He lived long enough to experience increasing recognition, although he has become much more widely written about since his death. Oakeshott refused an offer of being made a [[Companion of Honour]], for which he was proposed by [[Margaret Thatcher]].<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.michael-oakeshott-association.org/aboutoak_thatcher.html |title=A Letter from Margaret Thatcher |last= |first= |date= |website=www.michael-oakeshott-association.org |publisher= |access-date=2016-12-04 |deadurl=bot: unknown |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20080526060822/http://www.michael-oakeshott-association.org/aboutoak_thatcher.html |archivedate=26 May 2008 |df= }}</ref>+
- +
-== Philosophy ==+
- +
-===Early works===+
-{{Expand section|date=January 2009}}+
-Oakeshott's early work, some of which has been published posthumously as ''What is History? And Other Essays'' (2004) and ''The Concept of a Philosophical Jurisprudence'' (2007), shows that he was more interested in the philosophical problems that derived from his historical studies than he was in the history, even though he was employed as a historian.+
- +
-===Philosophy and modes of experience===+
-Oakeshott published his first book, ''Experience and its Modes'', in 1933. He noted that the book owed much to [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel]] and [[F. H. Bradley]];<ref>Oakeshott, ''Experience and Its Modes'', p. 6</ref> commentators also noticed resemblances between this work and the ideas of thinkers such as [[R. G. Collingwood]]<ref>Paul Franco, ''Michael Oakeshott: An Introduction'', pp. 45–46</ref> and [[Georg Simmel]].<ref>Efraim Podoksik, ‘Ethics and the Conduct of Life in the old Georg Simmel and the young Michael Oakeshott’, ''Simmel Studies'' 17(2), 2007, pp. 197–221</ref>+
- +
-The book argued that our experience is usually modal, in the sense that we always have a governing perspective on the world, be it practical or theoretical. There are various theoretical approaches one may take to understanding the world: [[natural science]] and history for example are separate modes of experience. It was a mistake, he declared, to treat history as if it ought to be practised on the model of the natural sciences.+
- +
-Philosophy, however, is not a modal interest. At this stage of his career, he saw philosophy as the world seen ''sub specie aeternitatis'', literally, 'under the aspect of eternity', free from presuppositions, whereas science and history and the practical mode relied on certain assumptions. Later (there is some disagreement about exactly when), Oakeshott adopted a pluralistic view of the various modes of experience, with philosophy just one 'voice' amongst others, though it retained its self-scrutinizing character.+
- +
-The dominating principles of scientific and historical thought were quantity (the world ''sub specie quantitatis'') and being in the past (the world ''sub specie praeteritorum''), respectively. Oakeshott distinguished the academic perspective on the past from the practical, in which the past is seen in terms of its relevance to ''our'' present and future. His insistence on the autonomy of history places him close to Collingwood, who also argued for the autonomy of historical knowledge.+
- +
-The practical world view (the world ''sub specie voluntatis'') presupposed the ideas of will and of value in terms of which practical action in the arenas of politics, economics, and ethics made sense. Because all action is conditioned by presuppositions, Oakeshott was inclined to see any attempt to change the world as reliant upon a scale of values, which themselves presuppose a context of experience. Even the conservative disposition to maintain the status quo relies upon managing inevitable change, he would later elaborate in his essay 'On Being Conservative'.+
- +
-===Post-war essays===+
-{{Conservatism sidebar |People}}+
-During this period Oakeshott published what became his best known work during his lifetime, the collection entitled ''Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays'' (1962). Some of the polemics against the direction post-[[World War II]] Britain was taking, in particular the acceptance of [[socialism]], gained Oakeshott a reputation as a conservative, seeking to uphold the importance of tradition, and sceptical about [[rationalism]] and fixed [[ideology|ideologies]]. [[Bernard Crick]] described him as a 'lonely [[Nihilism|nihilist]]'.<ref>Bernard Crick, ‘The World of Michael Oakeshott: Or the Lonely Nihilist’, ''Encounter'', 20 (June 1963), pp. 65–74</ref>+
- +
-Oakeshott's opposition to what he considered Utopian political projects is summed by his use of the analogy (possibly borrowed from the [[George Savile, 1st Marquess of Halifax|Marquess of Halifax]], a 17th-century English author whom he admired) of a ship of state which has "neither starting-place nor appointed destination...[and where] the enterprise is to keep afloat on an even keel".<ref>Oakeshott, Michael. ''Rationalism in Politics''. London: Methuen, 1962: p. 127; [https://books.google.com/books?id=2YbevnCXAhgC&pg=PA120]</ref> He was a critic of the Cambridge historian [[E. H. Carr]], historian of Soviet Russia, claiming that Carr had an uncritical attitude towards the [[Bolshevik]] regime, taking some of its propaganda at face value.<ref>M. Oakeshott, Review of E. H. Carr, ''The New Society'', in ''Times Literary Supplement'' (12 October 1951)</ref>+
- +
-===''On Human Conduct'' and Oakeshott's political theory===+
-In his essay "On Being Conservative" (1956)<ref>''Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays'' (London: Methuen,1962), pp. 168–96</ref> Oakeshott explained what he regarded as the conservative disposition: "To be conservative ... is to prefer the familiar to the unknown, to prefer the tried to the untried, fact to mystery, the actual to the possible, the limited to the unbounded, the near to the distant, the sufficient to the superabundant, the convenient to the perfect, present laughter to utopian bliss."+
- +
-Oakeshott's political philosophy, as advanced in ''On Human Conduct'' (1975), is free of any form of [[political party|party politics]]. The book's first part ("On the Theoretical Understanding of Human Conduct") develops a [[theory]] of human action as the exercise of intelligent [[agency (philosophy)|agency]] in activities such as wanting and choosing, the second ("On the Civil Condition") discusses the formal conditions of association appropriate to such intelligent agents, described as "civil" or legal association, and the third ("On the Character of a Modern European State") examines how far this understanding of human association has affected politics and political ideas in post-Renaissance [[European history]].+
- +
-Oakeshott suggests that there had been two major modes or understandings of human social organization. In the first, which he calls "enterprise association" (or ''universitas''), the state is understood as imposing some universal purpose ([[Profit (economics)|profit]], [[salvation]], progress, racial domination) on its subjects. By contrast, "civil association" (or ''societas'') is primarily a legal relationship in which laws impose obligatory conditions of action but do not require choosing one action rather than another.+
- +
-The complex, often technical style of ''On Human Conduct'' found few readers, and its initial reception was mostly one of bafflement. Oakeshott, who rarely responded to critics, used an article in the journal ''Political Theory'' to reply sardonically to some of the contributions made at a symposium on the book.<ref>M. Oakeshott, "On Misunderstanding Human Conduct: A Reply to My Critics," ''Political Theory'', 4 (1976), pp. 353–67.</ref>+
- +
-In his posthumously-published ''The Politics of Faith and the Politics of Scepticism'', Oakeshott describes enterprise and civil association in different terms. Here, an enterprise association is seen as based in a fundamental faith in human ability to ascertain and grasp some universal "good" (i.e. the Politics of Faith), and civil association is seen as based in a fundamental scepticism about human ability to either ascertain or achieve this good (i.e. the Politics of Scepticism). Oakeshott considers power (especially technological power) as a necessary prerequisite for the Politics of Faith, because a) it allows people to believe they can achieve something great (e.g. something universally good), and b) it allows them to implement the policies necessary to achieve their goal. The Politics of Scepticism, on the other hand, rests on the idea that government should concern itself with preventing bad things from happening rather than enabling ambiguously good events.+
- +
-Oakeshott employs the analogy of the [[adverb]] to describe the kind of restraint law involves. To him, laws prescribe "adverbial conditions": they condition our actions, but do not determine the substantive ends of our choices. For example, the law against murder is not a law against killing as such, but only a law against killing "murderously". Or, to choose a more trivial example, the law does not dictate that I have a car, but if I do, I must drive it on the same side of the road as everybody else. This contrasts with the rules of enterprise association in which those actions required by the governing are made compulsory for all.+
- +
-===Philosophy of history===+
-The final work Oakeshott published in his own lifetime, ''On History'' (1983) returned to the idea that history is a distinct mode of experience, but built on the theory of action developed for ''On Human Conduct''. Much of ''On History'' had in fact been written at the same time, in the early 1970s.+
- +
-During the mid-1960s, Oakeshott declared an admiration for [[Wilhelm Dilthey]], one of the pioneers of [[hermeneutics]]. ''On History'' can be interpreted as an essentially [[neo-Kantian]] enterprise of working out the conditions of the possibility of historical knowledge, work that Dilthey had begun.+
- +
-The first three essays set out the distinction between the present of historical experience and the present of practical experience, as well as the concepts of historical situation, historical event, and what is meant by change in history. ''On History'' includes an essay on [[jurisprudence]] ('The Rule of Law'). It also included a retelling of ''[[The Tower of Babel]]'' in a modern setting<ref>Reprinted as {{cite book |last=Oakeshott |first=Michael |chapter=The tower of Babel |editor-last=Clarke | editor-first=S.G. | editor-last2=Simpson | editor-first2=E. | title=Anti-Theory in Ethics and Moral Conservatism | publisher=State University of New York Press | series=SUNY Series in Ethical Theory | year=1989 | isbn=978-0-88706-912-3 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xnOMf9Yr0kgC&pg=PA185 | access-date=25 May 2018 | page=185ff.}}</ref> in which Oakeshott expresses disdain for human willingness to sacrifice individuality, culture, and quality of life for grand collective projects. He attributes this behaviour to fascination with novelty, persistent dissatisfaction, greed, and lack of self-reflection.<ref name="Corey 2006 p. 130">{{cite book | last=Corey | first=E.C. | title=Michael Oakeshott on Religion, Aesthetics, and Politics | publisher=University of Missouri Press | series=Eric Voegelin Institute series in political philosophy | year=2006 | isbn=978-0-8262-6517-3 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-QdCmqFe3a4C&pg=PA130 | page=129-131}}</ref>+
- +
-===Other works===+
-Oakeshott's other works included a reader on ''The Social and Political Doctrines of Contemporary Europe'' consisting of selected texts illustrating the main doctrines of [[liberalism]], [[Nazism|national socialism]], [[fascism]], [[communism]], and [[Roman Catholicism]] (1939). He was editor of an edition of [[Thomas Hobbes]]'s ''[[Leviathan (Hobbes book)|Leviathan]]'' (1946), for which he provided an introduction recognized as a significant contribution to the literature by later scholars such as [[Quentin Skinner]]. Several of his essays on Hobbes were published during 1975 as ''Hobbes on Civil Association''. He wrote, with his Cambridge colleague [[Guy Griffith]], ''A Guide to the Classics, or How to Pick The Derby Winner'' (1936), a guide to the principles of successful betting on horse-racing; this was his only non-academic work. He was the author of well over 150 essays and reviews, most of which have yet to be republished.+
- +
-Just before he died, Oakeshott approved two edited collections of his works, ''The Voice of Liberal Learning'' (1989), a collection of his essays on education, and a second, revised and expanded edition of ''Rationalism in Politics'' itself (1991). Posthumous collections of his writings include ''Morality and Politics in Modern Europe'' (1993), a lecture series he gave at [[Harvard]] in 1958, ''Religion, Politics, and the Moral Life'' (1993), essays mostly from his early and middle periods, ''The Politics of Faith and the Politics of Scepticism'' (1996), a manuscript from the 1950s contemporary with much of the material in ''Rationalism in Politics'' but written in a more considered tone.+
- +
-The bulk of his papers are now in the Oakeshott archive at the [[London School of Economics]]. Further volumes of posthumous writings are in preparation, as is a biography, and during the first decade of the 21st century a series of monographs devoted to his work were published.+
- +
-== Bibliography ==+
-* 1933. ''Experience and Its Modes''. Cambridge University Press+
-* 1936. ''A Guide to the Classics, or, How to Pick the Derby''. With G.T. Griffith. London: Faber and Faber+
-* 1939. ''The Social and Political Doctrines of Contemporary Europe''. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press+
-* 1941. ''The Social and Political Doctrines of Contemporary Europe'', 2nd edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press+
-* 1942. ''The Social and Political Doctrines of Contemporary Europe'' with five additional prefaces by F.A. Ogg. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press+
-* 1947. ''A New Guide to the Derby: How to Pick the Winner''. With G.T. Griffith. London: Faber and Faber+
-* 1955. ''La Idea de Gobierno en la Europa Moderna''. Madrid: Ateneo+
-* 1962. ''Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays''. London: Methuen (Expanded edition – 1991, by Liberty Fund)+
-* 1966. ''Rationalismus in der Politik''. (trans. K. Streifthau) Neuwied und Berlin: Luchterhard+
-* 1975. ''On Human Conduct''. Oxford: Oxford University Press+
-* 1975. ''Hobbes on Civil Association''. Oxford: Basil Blackwell+
-* 1983. ''On History and Other Essays''. Basil Blackwell+
-* 1985. ''La Condotta Umana''. Bologna: Società Editrice il Mulino+
-* 1989. ''The Voice of Liberal Learning''. New Haven and London: Yale University Press+
- +
-===Posthumous===+
-* 1991. ''Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays''. Indianapolis: Liberty Press+
-* 1993. ''Morality and Politics in Modern Europe''. New Haven: Yale University Press+
-* 1993. ''Religion, Politics, and the Moral Life''. New Haven: Yale University Press+
-* 1996. ''The Politics of Faith and the Politics of Skepticism''. New Haven: Yale University Press+
-* 2000. ''Zuversicht und Skepsis: Zwei Prinzipien neuzeitlicher Politik''. (trans. C. Goldmann). Berlin: Fest+
-* 2004. ''What Is History? And Other Essays''. Thorverton: Imprint Academic+
-* 2006. ''Lectures in the History of Political Thought''. Thorverton: Imprint Academic+
-* 2007. ''The Concept of a Philosophical Jurisprudence: Essays and Reviews 1926–51''. Thorverton: Imprint Academic+
-* 2008. ''The Vocabulary of a Modern European State: Essays and Reviews 1952–88''. Thorverton: Imprint Academic+
-* 2010. ''Early Political Writings 1925–30''. Thorverton: Imprint Academic+
- +
-== References ==+
-{{reflist}}+
- +
-== Further reading ==+
-* Robert Grant, ''Oakeshott'' (The Claridge Press, 1990)+
-* [[Terry Nardin]], ''[http://www.psupress.psu.edu/books/titles/0-271-02156-X.html The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott]'' (Penn State, 2001, {{ISBN|0-271-02156-X}})+
-* Efraim Podoksik, ''[http://www.imprint.co.uk/idealists/jcsmainframe.html#podoksik In Defence of Modernity: Vision and Philosophy in Michael Oakeshott]'' (Imprint Academic, 2003, {{ISBN|0-907845-66-5}})+
-* [[Paul Franco]], ''Michael Oakeshott: An Introduction'' (Yale, 2004, {{ISBN|0-300-10404-9}})+
-* Corey Abel & Timothy Fuller, eds. ''The Intellectual Legacy of Michael Oakeshott'' (Imprint Academic, 2005, {{ISBN|1-84540-009-7}})+
-* Elizabeth Campbell Corey, ''Michael Oakeshott on Religion, Aesthetics, and Politics'' (University of Missouri Press, 2006, {{ISBN|978-0826216403}})+
-* Till Kinzel, ''Michael Oakeshott. Philosoph der Politik (Perspektiven, 9)'' (Antaios, 2007, {{ISBN|978-3935063098}})+
-* [[Andrew Sullivan]], ''[http://www.imprint.co.uk/idealists/jcsmainframe.html#oakeshott Intimations Pursued: The Voice of Practice in the Conversation of Michael Oakeshott]'' (Imprint Academic, 2007)+
-* Corey Abel, ed, ''The meanings of Michael Oakeshott's Conservatism'' (Imprint Academic, 2010, {{ISBN|978-1845402181}})+
-* Efraim Podoksik, ed, ''The Cambridge Companion to Oakeshott'' (Cambridge University Press, 2012) {{ISBN|978-0521764674}}. {{OCLC|770694299}}+
-* Paul Franco & Leslie Marsh, eds, ''[http://www.psupress.org/books/titles/978-0-271-05407-0.html A Companion to Michael Oakeshott]'' (Penn State University Press, 2012) {{ISBN|978-0271054070}}. {{OCLC|793497138}}+
-* {{cite book|author=Gene Callahan|authorlink=Gene Callahan (economist)|title=Oakeshott on Rome and America|year=2012|publisher=Exeter: Imprint Academic|location=Charlottesville, VA|isbn=978-1845403133|pages=227 |oclc= 800863300}}+
- +
-== External links ==+
-{{Wikiquote}}+
-* [https://web.archive.org/web/20080526060822/http://www.michael-oakeshott-association.org/ Michael Oakeshott Association]+
-* [https://web.archive.org/web/20080514211157/http://www.michael-oakeshott-association.org/bibliography.htm The Michael Oakeshott Bibliography]+
-* Michael Oakeshott, [https://web.archive.org/web/20041205054654/http://www.mugu.com/cgi-bin/Upstream/oakeshott-rationalism-politics "Rationalism in Politics"]. ''Cambridge Journal,'' Volume I, 1947 (broken link – go through your State or Provincial library's subscription service)+
-* [http://archives.lse.ac.uk/TreeBrowse.aspx?src=CalmView.Catalog&field=RefNo&key=OAKESHOTT Catalogue of the Oakeshott papers] at the [https://web.archive.org/web/20070618035533/http://www.lse.ac.uk/library/archive/Default.htm Archives Division] of the [[London School of Economics]].+
-* {{C-SPAN|oakeshottmichael}}+
- +
-{{Social and political philosophy}}+
-{{Conservatism footer}}+
- +
-{{Authority control}}+
- +
-{{DEFAULTSORT:Oakeshott, Michael}}+
-[[Category:1901 births]]+
-[[Category:1990 deaths]]+
-[[Category:Alumni of Gonville and Caius College, Cambridge]]+
-[[Category:Academics of the London School of Economics]]+
-[[Category:20th-century British philosophers]]+
-[[Category:English philosophers]]+
-[[Category:English political theorists]]+
-[[Category:Historians of political thought]]+
-[[Category:Idealists]]+
-[[Category:People educated at St George's School, Harpenden]]+
-[[Category:Conservatism]]+
-[[Category:Hobbes scholars]]+
-[[Category:20th-century historians]]+
-[[Category:Fellows of the British Academy]]+
-[[Category:Critics of Marxism]]+
-[[Category:Fellows of Nuffield College, Oxford]]+
- +
- +
-{{GFDL}}+

Current revision

  1. REDIRECT The British Academy

Template:R from move

Personal tools