Objectivity (science)  

From The Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia

(Difference between revisions)
Jump to: navigation, search
Revision as of 08:47, 2 April 2018
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

← Previous diff
Revision as of 08:47, 2 April 2018
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

Next diff →
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Template}} {{Template}}
-'''Objectivity''' can refer to:+'''Objectivity''' in science is a value that informs how science is practiced and how scientific truths are discovered. It is the idea that scientists, in attempting to uncover truths about the natural world, must aspire to eliminate personal biases, a priori commitments, emotional involvement, etc.
-* [[Objectivity (philosophy)]]+==History==
-* [[Objectivity (journalism)]]+ 
-* [[Objectivity (science)]]+Objectivity in science appeared in the mid-nineteenth century.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />{{rp|17}} In the early eighteenth century, before objectivity, there existed an epistemic virtue in science which [[Lorraine Daston]] and [[Peter Galison]] have called ''truth-to-nature''.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />{{rp|55–58}} This ideal was practiced by [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] [[Natural history|naturalists]] and scientific atlas-makers and involved active attempts to eliminate any idiosyncrasies in their representations of nature in order to create images thought best to represent “what truly is.”<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />{{rp|59–60}}<ref name="Representations">{{cite journal | url=http://www.nyu.edu/classes/bkg/methods/daston.pdf | title=The Image of Objectivity |author1=Daston, Lorraine |author2=Galison, Peter | journal=Representations |date=Autumn 1992 | volume=0 | issue=40 | pages=81–128 | doi=10.2307/2928741}}</ref>{{rp|84–85}} Judgment and skill were deemed necessary in order to determine the “typical,” “characteristic,” “ideal” or “average.”<ref name="Representations" />{{rp|87}} In practicing truth-to-nature naturalists did not seek to depict exactly what was seen; rather, they sought a reasoned image.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />{{rp|98}}
-* Objectivity in [[historiography]]+ 
 +In the latter half of the nineteenth century objectivity in science was born when a new practice of ''mechanical objectivity'' appeared.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />{{rp|121}} “‘Let nature speak for itself’ became the watchword of a new brand of scientific objectivity.”<ref name="Representations" />{{rp|81}} It was at this time that idealized representations of nature, which were previously seen as a virtue, were now seen as a vice.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />{{rp|120}} Scientists began to see it as their duty to actively restrain themselves from imposing their own projections onto nature.<ref name="Representations" />{{rp|81}} The aim was to liberate representations of nature from subjective, human interference and in order to achieve this [[scientists]] began using self-registering instruments, cameras, wax molds and other technological devices.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />{{rp|121}}
 + 
 +In the twentieth century ''trained judgment''<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />{{rp|309}} supplemented mechanical objectivity as scientists began to recognize that, in order for images or data to be of any use, scientists needed to be able to see scientifically; that is, to interpret images or data and identify and group them according to particular professional training, rather than to simply depict them mechanically.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />{{rp|311–314}} Since the latter half of the nineteenth century objectivity now came to involve a combination of trained judgment and mechanical objectivity.
 + 
 +==Objectivity in measurement==
 + 
 +Another methodological aspect is the avoidance of [[bias]], which can involve [[cognitive bias]], [[cultural bias]], or [[sampling bias]]. Methods for avoiding or overcoming such biases include [[random sampling]] and [[double-blind]] trials<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.pl/books?hl=pl&lr=&id=ItKeqNfgNW0C&oi=fnd&pg=PA1&dq=objectivity+in+sampling,+random+sampling&ots=pLasfy8tgH&sig=kenaqNz6_pIH98Ddmug1gNQQrfM&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q=objectivity%20in%20sampling,%20random%20sampling&f=false|title=The Essential Guide to Doing Research|last=O'Leary|first=Zina|date=2004-06-09|publisher=SAGE Publications|isbn=9780761941996|language=en}}</ref>. However, objectivity in measurement can be unobtainable in certain circumstances. Even the most quantitative social sciences such as [[economics]] employ measures that are constructs (conventions, to employ the term coined by [[Pierre Duhem]]). For instance, one can use different weighting schemes when calculating [[inflation]] rates. Applying different conventions (such as [[Paasche and Laspayres Indices|Paasche and Laspeyres indices]]) leads to obtaining diverging results<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Maziarz|first=Mariusz|date=2018|title=Objectivity - a Pipe Dream?|url=http://www.ethicsinfinance.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/01/Mariusz-Maziarz-Do-the-right-thing-incentivise-ethics.pdf|journal=Finance & the common good|volume=44-45|pages=64-78|via=}}</ref>.
 + 
 +==Objectivity in experimental set-up and interpretation==
 +Another methodological aspect is the avoidance of [[bias]], which can involve [[cognitive bias]], [[cultural bias]], or [[sampling bias]]. Methods for avoiding or overcoming such biases include [[random sampling]] and [[double-blind]] trials.{{Citation needed|date=January 2010}}
 + 
 +==Deliberate misrepresentation==
 +Next to unintentional but possibly systematic error, there is always the possibility of deliberate misrepresentation of scientific results, whether for gain, fame, or ideological motives. When such cases of scientific fraud come to light, they usually give rise to an [[academic scandal]], but it is unknown how much fraud goes undiscovered. However, for important results, other groups will try to repeat the experiment. If they consistently fail, they will bring these negative results into the scientific debate.{{Citation needed|date=January 2010}}
 + 
 +==The role of the scientific community==
 +Various scientific processes, such as [[peer review]]s, the discussions at [[scientific conference]]s, and other meetings where scientific results are presented, are part of a social process whose purpose is to strengthen the objective aspect of the scientific method.{{Citation needed|date=January 2010}}
 + 
 +==Critiques of scientific objectivity==
 +A critical argument on scientific objectivity and positivism is that all science has a degree of [[Antipositivism|interpretivism]].<ref name="History of Psychiatry">{{cite book | url=https://books.google.co.uk/books?id=64Y6wtqzs7IC&pg=PA29&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false | title=History of Psychiatry and Medical Psychology: With an Epilogue on Psychiatry and the Mind-Body Relation | publisher=Springer Science & Business Media |author1=Gach, John |author2=Wallace, Edwin R. | year=2010 | isbn=9780387347080}}</ref>{{rp|29}} In the 1920s, Percy Bridgman's [[The Logic of Modern Physics|operationalism]] was centered in such recognition.<ref name="History of Psychiatry" />{{rp|29}}
 + 
 +===Thomas Kuhn's ''The Structure of Scientific Revolutions''===
 +Based on a historical review of the development of certain scientific theories in his book, ''[[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions]]'', scientist and historian [[Thomas Kuhn]] raised some philosophical objections to claims of the possibility of scientific understanding being truly objective. In Kuhn's analysis, scientists in different disciplines organise themselves into ''de facto'' [[paradigm]]s, within which scientific research is done, junior scientists are educated, and scientific problems are determined.<ref name=Kuhn>{{Citation|last=Kuhn|first=Thomas S.|title=The Structure of Scientific Revolutions|year=1962|publisher=The University of Chicago Press|url=http://projektintegracija.pravo.hr/_download/repository/Kuhn_Structure_of_Scientific_Revolutions.pdf|accessdate=14 November 2014}}</ref>
 + 
 +When observational data arises which appears to contradict or [[falsify]] a given [[scientific paradigm]], scientists within that paradigm have not, historically, immediately rejected the paradigm in question (as Sir [[Karl Popper]]'s philosophical theory of [[falsificationism]] would have them do), but instead they have gone to considerable lengths to resolve the apparent conflict without rejecting the paradigm. Through ad hoc variations to the theory and sympathetic interpretation of the data, supporting scientists will resolve the apparent conundrum. In extreme cases, they may even ignore the data altogether.<ref name=Kuhn />
 + 
 +Thus, Kuhn argues, the failure of a scientific revolution is not an objectively measurable, deterministic event, but a far more contingent shift in social order. A paradigm will go into a crisis when a significant portion of the scientists working in the field lose confidence in the paradigm, regardless of their reasons for doing so. The corollary of this observation is that the primacy of a given paradigm is similarly contingent on the social order amongst scientists at the time it gains ascendancy.<ref name=Kuhn />
 + 
 +Kuhn's theory has been criticised by scientists such as [[Richard Dawkins]] and [[Alan Sokal]] as presenting a profoundly [[relativist]] view of scientific progress.{{Citation needed|date=January 2010}} In a postscript to the third edition of his book, Kuhn denied being a relativist.{{Citation needed|date=January 2010}}
 + 
 +===Donna Haraway's "situated knowledges"===
 +In "Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective" (1988) [[Donna Haraway]] argues that when we talk about objectivity in science and philosophy, traditionally we understand it as a kind of disembodied, transcendent "conquering gaze from nowhere,"<ref name="Situated Knowledges">{{cite journal | url=http://www.staff.amu.edu.pl/~ewa/Haraway,%20Situated%20Knowledges.pdf | title=Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective | author=Haraway, Donna | journal=Feminist Studies |date=Autumn 1988 | volume=14 | issue=3 | pages=575–599 | doi=10.2307/3178066}}</ref>{{rp|581}} in which the subject is split apart, distanced from and set above the object of inquiry.<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />{{rp|583–587}} She argues that this kind of objectivity is impossible to achieve; it is "an illusion, a god trick,"<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />{{rp|582}} and instead demands a re-thinking of objectivity in such a way that, while still striving for "faithful accounts of the real world,"<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />{{rp|579}} we must also acknowledge and make explicit our perspective and positioning within the world.<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />{{rp|581–582}} She calls this new kind of knowledge-making "situated knowledges."<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />{{rp|582}} Objectivity, she argues, "turns out to be about particular and specific embodiment and definitely not about the false vision promising transcendence of all limits and responsibility."<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />{{rp|583}} This new objectivity, then, "allows us to become answerable for what we learn how to see."<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />{{rp|583}} Thus Haraway is not only critiquing the idea that objectivity, as we have long understood it, is possible; she is also arguing that if we continue to approach knowledge-making in this way then we wash our hands of any responsibility for our truth claims. In contrast, she is arguing, approaching knowledge-making from an embodied perspective forces us to take responsibility for our truth claims.
 + 
 +==References==
 +{{reflist}}
 + 
 +==Sources==
 +*Dawkins, Richard. (2003). ''[[A Devil's Chaplain]]: Selected essays''. Phoenix.
 +*Kuhn, Thomas. (1962). ''The structure of scientific revolutions''. University of Chicago Press, 3rd Ed., 1996.
 +*Latour, Bruno. (1987). ''[[Science in Action (book)|Science in Action]]''. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
 +*Polanyi, M. (1958). ''[[Personal knowledge, towards a post-critical philosophy]]''. London: Routledge.
 +*Sokal, Alan & Bricmont, Jean. (1999). ''[[Intellectual Impostures]]: Postmodern philosophers’ abuse of science''. London: Profile Books.
-==See also== 
-* [[New Objectivity]], German art movement 
{{GFDL}} {{GFDL}}

Revision as of 08:47, 2 April 2018

Related e

Wikipedia
Wiktionary
Shop


Featured:

Objectivity in science is a value that informs how science is practiced and how scientific truths are discovered. It is the idea that scientists, in attempting to uncover truths about the natural world, must aspire to eliminate personal biases, a priori commitments, emotional involvement, etc.

Contents

History

Objectivity in science appeared in the mid-nineteenth century.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />Template:Rp In the early eighteenth century, before objectivity, there existed an epistemic virtue in science which Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison have called truth-to-nature.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />Template:Rp This ideal was practiced by Enlightenment naturalists and scientific atlas-makers and involved active attempts to eliminate any idiosyncrasies in their representations of nature in order to create images thought best to represent “what truly is.”<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />Template:Rp<ref name="Representations">Template:Cite journal</ref>Template:Rp Judgment and skill were deemed necessary in order to determine the “typical,” “characteristic,” “ideal” or “average.”<ref name="Representations" />Template:Rp In practicing truth-to-nature naturalists did not seek to depict exactly what was seen; rather, they sought a reasoned image.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />Template:Rp

In the latter half of the nineteenth century objectivity in science was born when a new practice of mechanical objectivity appeared.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />Template:Rp “‘Let nature speak for itself’ became the watchword of a new brand of scientific objectivity.”<ref name="Representations" />Template:Rp It was at this time that idealized representations of nature, which were previously seen as a virtue, were now seen as a vice.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />Template:Rp Scientists began to see it as their duty to actively restrain themselves from imposing their own projections onto nature.<ref name="Representations" />Template:Rp The aim was to liberate representations of nature from subjective, human interference and in order to achieve this scientists began using self-registering instruments, cameras, wax molds and other technological devices.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />Template:Rp

In the twentieth century trained judgment<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />Template:Rp supplemented mechanical objectivity as scientists began to recognize that, in order for images or data to be of any use, scientists needed to be able to see scientifically; that is, to interpret images or data and identify and group them according to particular professional training, rather than to simply depict them mechanically.<ref name="Daston Galison Objectivity" />Template:Rp Since the latter half of the nineteenth century objectivity now came to involve a combination of trained judgment and mechanical objectivity.

Objectivity in measurement

Another methodological aspect is the avoidance of bias, which can involve cognitive bias, cultural bias, or sampling bias. Methods for avoiding or overcoming such biases include random sampling and double-blind trials<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>. However, objectivity in measurement can be unobtainable in certain circumstances. Even the most quantitative social sciences such as economics employ measures that are constructs (conventions, to employ the term coined by Pierre Duhem). For instance, one can use different weighting schemes when calculating inflation rates. Applying different conventions (such as Paasche and Laspeyres indices) leads to obtaining diverging results<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>.

Objectivity in experimental set-up and interpretation

Another methodological aspect is the avoidance of bias, which can involve cognitive bias, cultural bias, or sampling bias. Methods for avoiding or overcoming such biases include random sampling and double-blind trials.Template:Citation needed

Deliberate misrepresentation

Next to unintentional but possibly systematic error, there is always the possibility of deliberate misrepresentation of scientific results, whether for gain, fame, or ideological motives. When such cases of scientific fraud come to light, they usually give rise to an academic scandal, but it is unknown how much fraud goes undiscovered. However, for important results, other groups will try to repeat the experiment. If they consistently fail, they will bring these negative results into the scientific debate.Template:Citation needed

The role of the scientific community

Various scientific processes, such as peer reviews, the discussions at scientific conferences, and other meetings where scientific results are presented, are part of a social process whose purpose is to strengthen the objective aspect of the scientific method.Template:Citation needed

Critiques of scientific objectivity

A critical argument on scientific objectivity and positivism is that all science has a degree of interpretivism.<ref name="History of Psychiatry">Template:Cite book</ref>Template:Rp In the 1920s, Percy Bridgman's operationalism was centered in such recognition.<ref name="History of Psychiatry" />Template:Rp

Thomas Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

Based on a historical review of the development of certain scientific theories in his book, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, scientist and historian Thomas Kuhn raised some philosophical objections to claims of the possibility of scientific understanding being truly objective. In Kuhn's analysis, scientists in different disciplines organise themselves into de facto paradigms, within which scientific research is done, junior scientists are educated, and scientific problems are determined.<ref name=Kuhn>Template:Citation</ref>

When observational data arises which appears to contradict or falsify a given scientific paradigm, scientists within that paradigm have not, historically, immediately rejected the paradigm in question (as Sir Karl Popper's philosophical theory of falsificationism would have them do), but instead they have gone to considerable lengths to resolve the apparent conflict without rejecting the paradigm. Through ad hoc variations to the theory and sympathetic interpretation of the data, supporting scientists will resolve the apparent conundrum. In extreme cases, they may even ignore the data altogether.<ref name=Kuhn />

Thus, Kuhn argues, the failure of a scientific revolution is not an objectively measurable, deterministic event, but a far more contingent shift in social order. A paradigm will go into a crisis when a significant portion of the scientists working in the field lose confidence in the paradigm, regardless of their reasons for doing so. The corollary of this observation is that the primacy of a given paradigm is similarly contingent on the social order amongst scientists at the time it gains ascendancy.<ref name=Kuhn />

Kuhn's theory has been criticised by scientists such as Richard Dawkins and Alan Sokal as presenting a profoundly relativist view of scientific progress.Template:Citation needed In a postscript to the third edition of his book, Kuhn denied being a relativist.Template:Citation needed

Donna Haraway's "situated knowledges"

In "Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective" (1988) Donna Haraway argues that when we talk about objectivity in science and philosophy, traditionally we understand it as a kind of disembodied, transcendent "conquering gaze from nowhere,"<ref name="Situated Knowledges">Template:Cite journal</ref>Template:Rp in which the subject is split apart, distanced from and set above the object of inquiry.<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />Template:Rp She argues that this kind of objectivity is impossible to achieve; it is "an illusion, a god trick,"<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />Template:Rp and instead demands a re-thinking of objectivity in such a way that, while still striving for "faithful accounts of the real world,"<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />Template:Rp we must also acknowledge and make explicit our perspective and positioning within the world.<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />Template:Rp She calls this new kind of knowledge-making "situated knowledges."<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />Template:Rp Objectivity, she argues, "turns out to be about particular and specific embodiment and definitely not about the false vision promising transcendence of all limits and responsibility."<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />Template:Rp This new objectivity, then, "allows us to become answerable for what we learn how to see."<ref name="Situated Knowledges" />Template:Rp Thus Haraway is not only critiquing the idea that objectivity, as we have long understood it, is possible; she is also arguing that if we continue to approach knowledge-making in this way then we wash our hands of any responsibility for our truth claims. In contrast, she is arguing, approaching knowledge-making from an embodied perspective forces us to take responsibility for our truth claims.

References

Template:Reflist

Sources




Unless indicated otherwise, the text in this article is either based on Wikipedia article "Objectivity (science)" or another language Wikipedia page thereof used under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License; or on research by Jahsonic and friends. See Art and Popular Culture's copyright notice.

Personal tools