Meinong's jungle  

From The Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia

(Difference between revisions)
Jump to: navigation, search
Revision as of 16:39, 21 April 2018
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

← Previous diff
Revision as of 16:39, 21 April 2018
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

Next diff →
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Template}} {{Template}}
-In the [[philosophy of language]], an '''empty name''' is a [[proper names|proper name]] that has no [[sense and reference|referent]].+'''Meinong's jungle''' is the name given to the repository of non-existent entities in the [[ontology]] of [[Alexius Meinong]].
- +
-The ''problem of empty names'' is that empty names have a meaning that it seems they shouldn't have. The name "[[Pegasus]]" is empty; there is nothing to which it refers. Yet, though there is no Pegasus, we know what the sentence "Pegasus has two wings" means. We can even understand the sentence "There is no such thing as Pegasus." But, what can the meaning of a proper name be, except the object to which it refers?+
- +
-There are three broad ways which philosophers have tried to approach this problem.+
- +
-# The [[Meaning (linguistic)|meaning]] of a proper name is not the same as the object (if there is any) it refers to. Hence, though "Pegasus" refers to nothing, it still has a meaning. The German philosopher [[Gottlob Frege]] seems to have held a theory of this sort. He says that the sentence "Odysseus was set ashore at Ithaca while sound asleep" obviously has a sense. ... the thought [expressed by that sentence] remains the same whether "Odysseus" has reference or not." [[Bertrand Russell]] may also have held a similar theory, that a proper name is a disguised [[definite description]] that signifies some unique characteristic. If any object has this characteristic feature, the name has a referent. Otherwise it is empty. Perhaps "[[Aristotle]]" means "the teacher of [[Alexander the Great|Alexander]]". Since there was such a person, "Aristotle" refers to that person. By contrast, "Pegasus" may mean "the winged horse of [[Bellerophon]]". Since there was no such horse, the name has no referent. This is the so-called [[theory of descriptions|description theory of names]]. The difficulty with this account is that we may always use a proper name to deny that the individual bearing the name actually has some characteristic feature. So, we can meaningfully say that Aristotle was not the teacher of Alexander. But if "Aristotle" ''means'' "teacher of Alexander", it would follow that this assertion is self-contradictory, which it is not. [[Saul Kripke]] proposed this argument in a series of influential papers in the 1970s. Another difficulty is that different people may have different ideas about the defining characteristics of any individual. Yet we all understand what the name means. The sole information carried by the name seems to be the [[Identity (philosophy)|identity]] of the individual that it belongs to. This information therefore cannot be descriptive, it cannot describe the individual. As [[John Stuart Mill]] argued, a proper name tells us the identity of its bearer, without telling us anything else about it. Naming is rather like ''pointing''.+
-# A theory that became influential following Kripke's attack is that empty proper names, have, strictly speaking, no meaning. This is the so-called [[Direct reference|direct-reference]] theory. Versions of this theory have been defended by [[Keith Donnellan]], [[David Kaplan (philosopher)|David Kaplan]], [[Nathan Salmon]], [[Scott Soames]] and others. The problem with the direct-reference theory is that names appear to be meaningful independently of whether they are empty. Furthermore, negative existential statements using empty names are both true and apparently meaningful. How can "Pegasus does not exist" be true if the name "Pegasus", as used in that sentence, has no meaning?+
-# There are no empty names. All names have a referent. The difficulty with this theory is how to distinguish names like "Pegasus" from names like "Aristotle". Any coherent account of this distinction seems to require that there are, i.e. there exist, objects that do not exist. Given that "Pegasus does not exist" is true, it follows that the referent of "Pegasus" does not exist. Hence there is something—the referent of "Pegasus"—that does not exist.+
-Some philosophers, such as [[Alexius Meinong]] have argued that there are two senses of the verb "exists", exemplified by the sentence "there are things that do not exist". The first, signified by "there are", is the so-called "wide sense", including Pegasus, the golden mountain, the round square, and so on. The second, signified by "exist" is the so-called "narrow sense", encompassing only things that are real or existent. The difficulty with this "two sense" theory is that there is no strong evidence that there really are two such distinct senses of the verb "to be".+
== See also == == See also ==
-*[[Meinong's jungle]]+*[[Empty name]], a name without a referent
-*[[Meta-ontology]]+*[[Fictionalism]], a theory which holds that one can talk about fictional objects without being committed to their existence
-*[[Ontological commitment]]+*[[Noneism]], the philosophical belief that there are things that do not exist
*[[Plato's beard]] *[[Plato's beard]]
{{GFDL}} {{GFDL}}

Revision as of 16:39, 21 April 2018

Related e

Wikipedia
Wiktionary
Shop


Featured:

Meinong's jungle is the name given to the repository of non-existent entities in the ontology of Alexius Meinong.

See also

  • Empty name, a name without a referent
  • Fictionalism, a theory which holds that one can talk about fictional objects without being committed to their existence
  • Noneism, the philosophical belief that there are things that do not exist
  • Plato's beard




Unless indicated otherwise, the text in this article is either based on Wikipedia article "Meinong's jungle" or another language Wikipedia page thereof used under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License; or on research by Jahsonic and friends. See Art and Popular Culture's copyright notice.

Personal tools