Mimesis  

From The Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia

(Difference between revisions)
Jump to: navigation, search
Revision as of 12:28, 20 October 2010
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

← Previous diff
Current revision
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

Line 1: Line 1:
 +{| class="toccolours" style="float: left; margin-left: 1em; margin-right: 2em; font-size: 85%; background:#c6dbf7; color:black; width:30em; max-width: 40%;" cellspacing="5"
 +| style="text-align: left;" |
 +"From childhood [[human|men]] have an instinct for [[Representation (arts)|representation]], and in this respect, differs from the other animals that he is far more [[mimesis|imitative]] and learns his first lessons by representing things." -''[[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]]'', Aristotle, tr. W.H. Fyfe
 +|}
 +[[Image:The Artist Moved by the Grandeur of Ancient Ruins.jpg|thumb|right|200px|
 +''[[The artist's despair before the grandeur of ancient ruins]]'' ([[1778]]-[[1779|79]]) by [[Fuseli|Henry Fuseli]]]]
 +[[Image:Mona Lisa Smoking a Pipe.jpg|thumb|right|200px|''[[Mona Lisa Smoking a Pipe]]'' by [[Eugène Bataille]]]]
 +
{{Template}} {{Template}}
-:[[User:Jahsonic/2007 notes on mimesis]] 
-:Related: [[copy]] - [[derivative]] - [[mimesis]] - [[plagiarism]] - [[imitation]] - [[reproduction]] 
-'''Mimesis''' ('''μίμησις''' from '''μιμεîσθαι''') in its simplest context means [[imitation]] or [[Representation (arts)|representation]] in [[Greek language|Greek]]. 
-==History== +'''Mimesis''' (from [[wiktionary:μιμοῦμαι|μιμεῖσθαι]]) is a [[Critical theory|critical]] and [[philosophical]] term that carries a wide range of meanings, which include: [[imitation]], [[Representation (arts)|representation]], [[mimicry]], ''imitatio'', nonsensuous [[similarity]], the act of [[Resemblance|resembling]], the act of expression, and the [[Impression management|presentation of the self]]. Mimesis has been theorised by [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], [[Philip Sidney]], [[Samuel Taylor Coleridge]], [[Sigmund Freud]], [[Walter Benjamin]], [[Theodor Adorno]], [[Erich Auerbach]], [[Luce Irigaray]] and [[Michael Taussig]].
-Both [[Plato]] and [[Aristotle]] saw, in mimesis (Greek μίμησις), the [[Representation (arts)|representation]] of [[nature]]. Plato wrote about mimesis in both ''[[Ion (dialogue)|Ion]]'' and ''[[Republic (Plato)|The Republic]]'' (Books I & II and Book X). In ''Ion'' he states that poetry is the art of divine madness, or inspiration. Because of this, it is not the function of the poet to convey the truth. As Plato has it, truth is the concern of the philosopher only. As culture in those days did not consist in the solitary reading of books, but in the listening to 'performances', the recitals of orators or the acting out by classical actors of tragedy, etc., Plato maintained in his critique that theatre was not sufficient in conveying the truth. He was concerned that actors or orators were thus able to persuade an audience by rhetoric rather than by telling the truth.+==Classical definitions==
 +===Plato===
 +Both [[Plato]] and [[Aristotle]] saw in mimesis (Greek ''μίμησις'') the [[Representation (arts)|representation]] of [[nature]]. Plato wrote about mimesis in both ''[[Ion (dialogue)|Ion]]'' and ''[[Republic (Plato)|The Republic]]'' (Books II, III and X). In ''Ion'', he states that [[poetry]] is the art of [[Theia mania|divine madness]], or inspiration. Because the poet is subject to this divine madness, it is not his/her function to convey the [[truth]]. As Plato has it, truth is the concern of the philosopher only. As culture in those days did not consist in the [[solitary reading]] of books, but in the listening to performances, the recitals of orators (and poets), or the acting out by classical actors of tragedy, Plato maintained in his critique that theatre was not sufficient in conveying the truth. He was concerned that actors or orators were thus able to persuade an audience by [[rhetoric]] rather than by telling the truth.
-In Book I and II of his ''Republic'' Plato argues that poets have no place in the ideal state, and that a philosopher ought to hold the highest role as Philosopher King. In Book X he gives the reasons for this opinion - and this is the part of his theory that is known by most people. Plato thought all creation was [[imitation]], and so the gods' [[creation (theology)|creation]] was an imitation of the truth and essence of nature, and an artist's re-presentation of this god-created reality was twice-removed representation, leading away from the Ideal. This is why Plato considers poets, painters, and other representational artists "two steps removed from the truth."+In Book II of ''The Republic'', Plato describes [[Socrates]]' dialogue with his pupils. Socrates warns we should not seriously regard poetry as being capable of attaining the truth and that we who listen to poetry should be on our guard against its seductions, since the poet has no place in our idea of God.
-Aristotle's [[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]] is often referred to as the counterpart to this Platonic conception of poetry. Aristotle was not against literature as such; he stated that human beings are mimetic beings, feeling an urge to create texts (art) that reflect and represent reality.+In developing this in Book X, Plato tells of [[Socrates's metaphor of the three beds]]: one bed exists as an idea made by God (the [[Platonic ideal]]); one is made by the carpenter, in imitation of God's idea; one is made by the artist in imitation of the carpenter's.
-Aristotle considered it important that there be a certain distance between the work of art on the one hand and life on the other; we draw knowledge and consolation from tragedies only because they do not happen to us. Without this distance, tragedy could not give rise to [[catharsis]]. However, it is equally important that the text causes the audience to identify with the characters and the events in the text, and unless this identification occurs, it does not touch us, as an audience. Aristotle holds that it is through simulated representation, mimesis, that we respond to the acting on the stage which is conveying to us what the characters feel, so that we may empathize with them in this way through the mimetic form of dramatic roleplay. It is the task of the dramatist to produce the tragic enactment in order to accomplish this empathy by means of what is taking place on stage.+So the artist's bed is [[twice removed from the truth]]. The copiers only touch on a small part of things as they really are, where a bed may appear differently from various points of view, looked at obliquely or directly, or differently again in a mirror. So painters or poets, though they may paint or describe a carpenter or any other maker of things, know nothing of the carpenter's (the craftsman's) art, and though the better painters or poets they are, the more faithfully their works of art will resemble the reality of the carpenter making a bed, nonetheless the imitators will still not attain the truth (of [[God's creation]]).
-In short, catharsis can only be achieved if we see something that is both recognizable and distant. Aristotle argued that literature is more interesting as a means of learning than history, because history deals with specific facts that have happened, and which are contingent, whereas literature, although sometimes based on history, deals with events that could have taken place, or ought to have taken place.+The poets, beginning with Homer, far from improving and educating humanity, do not possess the knowledge of craftsmen and are mere imitators who copy again and again images of virtue and rhapsodise about them, but never reach the truth in the way the superior philosophers do.
-Aristotle thought of [[drama]] as being "an imitation of an action," that of [[tragedy]] as of "falling from a higher to a lower estate", and so being removed to a less ideal situation in more ''tragic'' circumstances than before. He posited the [[fictional character|characters]] in tragedy as being better than the average human being, and those of [[comedy]] as being worse.+===Aristotle===
 +Similar to Plato's writings about mimesis, Aristotle also defined mimesis as the [[perfection]] and imitation of nature. Art is not only imitation but also the use of mathematical ideas and symmetry in the search for the perfect, the timeless, and contrasting being with becoming. Nature is full of change, decay, and cycles, but art can also search for what is everlasting and the first causes of natural phenomena. Aristotle wrote about the idea of [[four causes]] in nature. The first [[formal cause]] is like a [[blueprint]], or an immortal idea. The second cause is the material, or what a thing is made out of. The third cause is the process and the agent, in which the artist or creator makes the thing. The fourth cause is the good, or the purpose and end of a thing, known as [[Telos (philosophy)|telos]].
 +
 +Aristotle's ''[[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]]'' is often referred to as the counterpart to this Platonic conception of poetry. ''Poetics'' is his treatise on the subject of mimesis. Aristotle was not against literature as such; he stated that human beings are mimetic beings, feeling an urge to create texts (art) that reflect and represent reality.
-Aristotle's treatise on this subject is his [[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]].+Aristotle considered it important that there be a certain [[distance]] between the [[work of art]] on the one hand and life on the other; we draw knowledge and consolation from tragedies only because they do not happen to us. Without this distance, tragedy could not give rise to [[catharsis]]. However, it is equally important that the text causes the audience to identify with the characters and the events in the text, and unless this identification occurs, it does not touch us as an audience. Aristotle holds that it is through '''simulated representation''', mimesis, that we respond to the acting on the stage which is conveying to us what the characters feel, so that we may empathize with them in this way through the mimetic form of dramatic roleplay. It is the task of the dramatist to produce the tragic enactment in order to accomplish this empathy by means of what is taking place on stage.
-==Various aspects and contributions by other authors== +In short, catharsis can only be achieved if we see something that is both recognizable and distant. Aristotle argued that literature is more interesting as a means of learning than history, because history deals with specific facts that have happened, and which are contingent, whereas literature, although sometimes based on history, deals with events that could have taken place or ought to have taken place.
-[[Walter Kaufmann]] in ''[[Tragedy and Philosophy]]'' Ch.II suggests that we translate mimêsis in Aristotle’s Poetics as “make-believe”. +Aristotle thought of [[drama]] as being "an imitation of an action" and of [[tragedy]] as "falling from a higher to a lower estate" and so being removed to a less ideal situation in more ''tragic'' circumstances than before. He posited the [[fictional character|characters]] in tragedy as being better than the average human being, and those of [[comedy]] as being worse.
Michael Davis, a translator and commentator of Aristotle writes: Michael Davis, a translator and commentator of Aristotle writes:
-:"At first glance, mimêsis seems to be a stylizing of reality in which the ordinary features of our world are brought into focus by a certain exaggeration, the relationship of the imitation to the object it imitates being something like the relationship of dancing to walking. Imitation always involves selecting something from the continuum of experience, thus giving boundaries to what really has no beginning or end. Mimêsis involves a framing of reality that announces that what is contained within the frame is not simply real. Thus the more “real” the imitation the more fraudulent it becomes." (''The Poetry of Philosophy'', p.3) 
- 
-More recently [[Erich Auerbach]], [[Merlin Donald]], and [[René Girard]] have written about mimesis. 
- 
-[[Michael Taussig]], the anthropologist, in his book ''Mimesis and Alterity'' looks at the way people from one culture adopt another's nature and culture (mimesis), at the same time as distancing themselves from it (alterity). He describes how a legendary tribe, the 'white Indians', or Cuna, have adopted in various representations figures and images reminiscent of the white people they encountered in the past (without acknowledging doing so). 
- 
-Taussig, however, criticises anthropology for reducing yet another culture , that of the Cuna, for having been so impressed by their exotic (and superior) technologies of the Whites, that they raised them to the status of Gods. To Taussig, this reductionism is suspect, and he argues thus from both sides in his ''Mimesis and Alterity'', to see values in the anthropologists' perspective, at the same time as defending the independence of a lived culture from anthropological reductionism. (Taussig 1993:47,48) 
- 
-For a discussion of mimesis in seventeenth-century aesthetic discourse see: Williamson, Mark A. "The Martyrdom Paintings of Jusepe de Ribera:Catharsis and Transformation", PhD Dissertation, Binghamton University, Binghamton, New York 2000 (available online at myspace.com/markwilliamson13732) 
- 
-==Mimesis in contrast to diegesis== 
- 
-It was also Plato and Aristotle who contrasted mimesis with [[diegesis]]. In ''diegesis'' it is not the form in which a work of art represents reality but that in which the author is the speaker who is describing events in the narrative he presents to the audience.<br>It is in diegesis that the author addresses the audience or the readership directly as a narrator to express his freely creative art of the imagination, of fantasies and dreams in contrast to mimesis. Diegesis was thought of as ''telling'': the author narrating action indirectly and describing what is in the characters' minds and emotions, while mimesis is seen in terms of ''showing'' what is going on in the characters' inner thoughts and emotions through their external actions and their acting. 
- 
-==What it does== 
- 
-In the arts, mimesis is considered to be re-presenting the human [[emotion]]s in new ways and thus representing to the onlooker, listener or reader the inherent nature of these emotions and the psychological truth of the work of art. 
- 
- 
-== Mimesis and literary creation == 
- 
- 
-Mimesis is thus thought to be a means of perceiving the emotions of the characters on stage or in the book; or the truth of the figures as they appear in [[sculpture]] or in [[painting]]; or the emotions as they are being configured in music, and of their being recognised by the onlooker as part of their human condition. 
-[[Mimesis]] as opposed to [[catharsis]] are two basic notions on which [[Freud]] relies to explain the psychological intricacy of the relation between the author and his work, the [[hero]] and the reader/spectator as the process of literary creation is akin to that of dreaming awake. Charles Mauron starts from this fundamental theory to propose a structured method to analyse the unconscious roots and purpose of artistic creation. Identification and [[empathy]] are [[Unconscious mind|unconscious]] dynamic processes that account for the acting out of [[taboo]]s. The creator and the reader/spectator symbolically identify and expurgate similar repressed [[desire]]s, whether they be biographical or archetypal. Thus, when we read about [[Proust]]'s [[oral]] emotions reminding him of his aunt Leonie, we share a similar [[affect]]. The hero is but an [[avatar]] of the artist's [[double]].+:"At first glance, mimesis seems to be a stylizing of reality in which the ordinary features of our world are brought into focus by a certain exaggeration, the relationship of the imitation to the object it imitates being something like the relationship of dancing to walking. Imitation always involves selecting something from the continuum of experience, thus giving boundaries to what really has no beginning or end. ''Mimêsis'' involves a framing of reality that announces that what is contained within the frame is not simply real. Thus the more "real" the imitation the more fraudulent it becomes."
-[[:fr:mimesis]]+====Contrast to diegesis====
 +It was also Plato and Aristotle who contrasted mimesis with [[diegesis]] (Greek ''διήγησις''). Mimesis ''shows'', rather than ''tells'', by means of directly represented action that is enacted. Diegesis, however, is the ''telling'' of the [[Narrative|story]] by a [[narrator]]; the author narrates action indirectly and describes what is in the characters' minds and emotions. The narrator may speak as a particular character or may be the ''[[invisible narrator]]'' or even the ''[[all-knowing narrator]]'' who speaks from above in the form of commenting on the action or the characters.
-== Mimesis and the [[theatre]] ==+In Book III of his ''[[The Republic (Plato)|Republic]]'' (c. 373 BCE), the [[Ancient Greek philosopher]] [[Plato]] examines the style of poetry (the term includes [[comedy]], [[tragedy]], [[Epic poetry|epic]] and [[lyric poetry]]): All types narrate events, he argues, but by differing means. He distinguishes between narration or report (diegesis) and imitation or representation (mimesis). Tragedy and comedy, he goes on to explain, are wholly imitative types; the [[dithyramb]] is wholly narrative; and their combination is found in [[epic poetry]]. When reporting or narrating, "the poet is speaking in his own person; he never leads us to suppose that he is any one else"; when imitating, the poet produces an "assimilation of himself to another, either by the use of voice or gesture". In dramatic texts, the poet never speaks directly; in narrative texts, the poet speaks as himself or herself.
-A significant example of the intuitive use of this poetic function is the [[pantomime]] or '''play-within-the-play''' in [[Shakespeare]]'s ''[[Hamlet]]'': the acknowledged aim is to provoke [[Claudius]] and expose his guilt. But at the same time, this will be the only action Hamlet will be able to take: it dramatizes his inner conflict: through it, he both achieves the murderous desire and identifies with the murderer.+In his ''[[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]]'', the [[Ancient Greece|ancient Greek]] [[philosopher]] [[Aristotle]] argues that kinds of poetry (the term includes [[drama]], [[flute]] [[music]], and [[lyre]] music for Aristotle) may be differentiated in three ways: according to their ''medium'', according to their ''objects'', and according to their ''mode'' or ''manner'' (section I); "For the medium being the same, and the objects the same, the poet may imitate by narration—in which case he can either take another personality as Homer does, or speak in his own person, unchanged—or he may present all his characters as living and moving before us" (section III).
-==Examples==+Though they conceive of mimesis in quite different ways, its relation with diegesis is identical in Plato's and Aristotle's formulations; one represents, the other reports; one embodies, the other narrates; one transforms, the other indicates; one knows only a continuous present, the other looks back on a past.
-In [[sculpture]], mimesis manifests the three-dimensional plasticity of an [[image]] an onlooker has with which he can empathize within a given situation. In [[Rodin]]'s ''[[The Kiss (Rodin sculpture)|The Kiss]]'', for example, the protective arms of the male and seeming trustfulness of the female figure enclosed within her partner's limbs, down to the stance of their feet, is a position all humans would recognize immediately in that the trust and truth that permeates the erotic element of the [[statue]] is that which is entailed in the relationship of any man and woman in a similar situation.+In [[ludology]], mimesis is sometimes used to refer to the self-consistency of a represented world, and the availability of in-[[game]] rationalisations for elements of the gameplay. In this context, mimesis has an associated grade: highly self-consistent worlds that provide explanations for their puzzles and game mechanics are said to display a higher degree of mimesis. This usage can be traced back to the essay "Crimes Against Mimesis" by Roger Giner-Sorolla.
-In [[Picasso]]'s ''[[Guernica (painting)|Guernica]]'', the artist re-presents the destruction of life and the terror it causes in a way this kind of [[cubism|cubistic]] image lends itself to most dramatically. The fractured details of the composition, the tortured faces, the screams that may be almost audibly imagined, the terrified horse, the bull, the dismembered limbs: all these things help to make the picture most memorable for the truth it brings to the observer. However, the face of the woman holding a light may be seen either as a face of stoic resignation throwing light on the devastation, or a face of [[lucifer|luciferous]] evil swooping in malevolent satisfaction.+===Dionysian imitatio===
 +Three centuries after Aristotle's ''Poetics'', from 4th century BCE to 1st century BCE, the meaning of ''mimesis'' as a [[literary method]] had shifted from "imitation of nature" to "imitation of other authors." No historical record is left to explain the reason of this change, and [[Dionysius of Halicarnassus|Dionysius]]' work ''On mimesis'' (''On imitation'') got lost; most of this work contained advice on how to identify the most suitable writers to imitate and the best way to imitate them.
-In [[Ludwig van Beethoven|Beethoven]]'s "[[Symphony No. 6 (Beethoven)|6th Symphony]]" (the [[Pastoral]]), [[music]] re-presents the various stages of a stay in the country, of a person's emotions and moods that are metamorphosed into movements of music most faithfully corresponding to these emotions. Thus, the pleasurable anticipation on arrival in the country; the various happy scenes of their associating with countryfolk; a shepherd's [[song]]; [[birdsong]]s; a storm and the thankfulness after it is over; all will be observed and recognised readily by the audience.+Latin orators and rhetoricians adopted the literary method of Dionysius' ''imitatio'' and discarded Aristotle's ''mimesis''; the imitation literary approach is closely linked with the widespread observation that "everything has been said already," which was also stated by an Egyptian scribes around 2000 BCE. The ideal aim of this approach to literature was not [[originality]], but to surpass the predecessor by improving their writings and set the bar to a higher level.
-==Mimesis in Ludology==+==Samuel Taylor Coleridge==
 +Mimesis, or imitation, as he referred to it, was a crucial concept for [[Samuel Taylor Coleridge]]'s theory of the imagination. Coleridge begins his thoughts on imitation and poetry from Plato, Aristotle and [[Philip Sidney]], adopting their concept of imitation of nature instead of other writers. His significant departure from the earlier thinkers lies in him arguing that art does not reveal a unity of essence through its ability to achieve sameness with nature. Coleridge claims:
 +<blockquote>
 +[T]he composition of a poem is among the imitative arts; and that imitation, as opposed to copying, consists either in the interfusion of the SAME throughout the radically DIFFERENT, or the different throughout a base radically the same.
-In [[ludology]], mimesis is sometimes used to refer to the self-consistency of a represented world, and the availability of in-game rationalisations for elements of the gameplay. In this context mimesis has an associated grade: highly self-consistent worlds that provide explanations for their puzzles and game mechanics are said to display a higher degree of mimesis. +</blockquote>
 +Here, Coleridge opposes imitation to copying, the latter referring to [[William Wordsworth]]'s notion that poetry should duplicate nature by capturing actual speech. Coleridge instead argues that the unity of essence is revealed precisely through different materialities and media. Imitation, therefore, reveals the sameness of processes in nature.
-This usage can be traced back to the essay "Crimes against Mimesis".+==Luce Irigaray==
 +The French feminist [[Luce Irigaray]] used the term to describe a form of resistance where women imperfectly imitate stereotypes about themselves so as to show up these stereotypes and undermine them. This strategy is also known as [[strategic essentialism]].
-== Notes ==+==Michael Taussig==
-<!--See [[Wikipedia:Footnotes]] for an explanation of how to generate footnotes using the <references/> tags-->+In ''[[Mimesis and Alterity]]'' (1993), the [[Anthropology|anthropologist]] [[Michael Taussig]] examines the way that people from one culture adopt another's nature and culture (the process of mimesis) at the same time as distancing themselves from it (the process of [[alterity]]). He describes how a legendary tribe, the "white Indians", or [[Kuna (people)|Cuna]], have adopted in various representations figures and images reminiscent of the white people they encountered in the past (without acknowledging doing so).
-<div class="references-small"><references/></div>+
-==References== +Taussig, however, criticises anthropology for reducing yet another culture, that of the Cuna, for having been so impressed by their exotic (and superior) technologies of the whites, that they raised them to the status of Gods. To Taussig, this reductionism is suspect, and he argues thus from both sides in his ''Mimesis and Alterity'' to see values in the anthropologists' perspective, at the same time as defending the independence of a lived culture from anthropological reductionism. (Taussig 1993:47,48)
-* [[Erich Auerbach]], ''Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western Literature'', Princeton University Press, 1953 (with reprints).+==See also==
 +* [[Life imitating art]]
 +== References ==
 +* [[Erich Auerbach|Auerbach, Erich]]. 1953. ''[[Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western Literature]]''. Princeton: Princeton UP. ISBN 069111336X.
 +*[[Samuel Taylor Coleridge|Coleridge, S.T.]] 1983. Biographia Literaria. v.1 eds. James Engell and W. Jackson Bate. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP. ISBN 0-691-09874-3.
 +* Davis, Michael. 1999. ''The Poetry of Philosophy: On Aristotle's Poetics''. South Bend, Indiana: St Augustine's P. ISBN 1890318620.
 +* Elam, Keir. 1980. ''The Semiotics of Theatre and Drama''. New Accents Ser. London and New York: Methuen. ISBN 0416720609.
 +* Gebauer, Gunter, and Christoph Wulf. 1992. ''Mimesis: Culture—Art—Society.'' Trans. Don Reneau. Berkeley and London: U of California P, 1995. ISBN 0520084594.
 +* [[Walter Kaufmann (philosopher)|Kaufmann, Walter]]. 1992. ''Tragedy and Philosophy''. Princeton: Princeton UP. ISBN 0691020051.
 +* Pfister, Manfred. 1977. ''The Theory and Analysis of Drama''. Trans. John Halliday. European Studies in English Literature Ser. Cambridige: Cambridge UP, 1988. ISBN 052142383X.
 +* [[Władysław Tatarkiewicz|Tatarkiewicz, Władysław]]. 1980. ''A History of Six Ideas: An Essay in Aesthetics''. Trans. [[Christopher Kasparek]]. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. ISBN 9024722330.
 +* [[Michael Taussig|Taussig, Michael]]. 1993. ''Mimesis and Alterity: A Particular History of the Senses''. London and New York: Routledge. ISBN 0415906865.
{{GFDL}} {{GFDL}}

Current revision

"From childhood men have an instinct for representation, and in this respect, differs from the other animals that he is far more imitative and learns his first lessons by representing things." -Poetics, Aristotle, tr. W.H. Fyfe

Related e

Wikipedia
Wiktionary
Shop


Featured:

Mimesis (from μιμεῖσθαι) is a critical and philosophical term that carries a wide range of meanings, which include: imitation, representation, mimicry, imitatio, nonsensuous similarity, the act of resembling, the act of expression, and the presentation of the self. Mimesis has been theorised by Plato, Aristotle, Philip Sidney, Samuel Taylor Coleridge, Sigmund Freud, Walter Benjamin, Theodor Adorno, Erich Auerbach, Luce Irigaray and Michael Taussig.

Contents

Classical definitions

Plato

Both Plato and Aristotle saw in mimesis (Greek μίμησις) the representation of nature. Plato wrote about mimesis in both Ion and The Republic (Books II, III and X). In Ion, he states that poetry is the art of divine madness, or inspiration. Because the poet is subject to this divine madness, it is not his/her function to convey the truth. As Plato has it, truth is the concern of the philosopher only. As culture in those days did not consist in the solitary reading of books, but in the listening to performances, the recitals of orators (and poets), or the acting out by classical actors of tragedy, Plato maintained in his critique that theatre was not sufficient in conveying the truth. He was concerned that actors or orators were thus able to persuade an audience by rhetoric rather than by telling the truth.

In Book II of The Republic, Plato describes Socrates' dialogue with his pupils. Socrates warns we should not seriously regard poetry as being capable of attaining the truth and that we who listen to poetry should be on our guard against its seductions, since the poet has no place in our idea of God.

In developing this in Book X, Plato tells of Socrates's metaphor of the three beds: one bed exists as an idea made by God (the Platonic ideal); one is made by the carpenter, in imitation of God's idea; one is made by the artist in imitation of the carpenter's.

So the artist's bed is twice removed from the truth. The copiers only touch on a small part of things as they really are, where a bed may appear differently from various points of view, looked at obliquely or directly, or differently again in a mirror. So painters or poets, though they may paint or describe a carpenter or any other maker of things, know nothing of the carpenter's (the craftsman's) art, and though the better painters or poets they are, the more faithfully their works of art will resemble the reality of the carpenter making a bed, nonetheless the imitators will still not attain the truth (of God's creation).

The poets, beginning with Homer, far from improving and educating humanity, do not possess the knowledge of craftsmen and are mere imitators who copy again and again images of virtue and rhapsodise about them, but never reach the truth in the way the superior philosophers do.

Aristotle

Similar to Plato's writings about mimesis, Aristotle also defined mimesis as the perfection and imitation of nature. Art is not only imitation but also the use of mathematical ideas and symmetry in the search for the perfect, the timeless, and contrasting being with becoming. Nature is full of change, decay, and cycles, but art can also search for what is everlasting and the first causes of natural phenomena. Aristotle wrote about the idea of four causes in nature. The first formal cause is like a blueprint, or an immortal idea. The second cause is the material, or what a thing is made out of. The third cause is the process and the agent, in which the artist or creator makes the thing. The fourth cause is the good, or the purpose and end of a thing, known as telos.

Aristotle's Poetics is often referred to as the counterpart to this Platonic conception of poetry. Poetics is his treatise on the subject of mimesis. Aristotle was not against literature as such; he stated that human beings are mimetic beings, feeling an urge to create texts (art) that reflect and represent reality.

Aristotle considered it important that there be a certain distance between the work of art on the one hand and life on the other; we draw knowledge and consolation from tragedies only because they do not happen to us. Without this distance, tragedy could not give rise to catharsis. However, it is equally important that the text causes the audience to identify with the characters and the events in the text, and unless this identification occurs, it does not touch us as an audience. Aristotle holds that it is through simulated representation, mimesis, that we respond to the acting on the stage which is conveying to us what the characters feel, so that we may empathize with them in this way through the mimetic form of dramatic roleplay. It is the task of the dramatist to produce the tragic enactment in order to accomplish this empathy by means of what is taking place on stage.

In short, catharsis can only be achieved if we see something that is both recognizable and distant. Aristotle argued that literature is more interesting as a means of learning than history, because history deals with specific facts that have happened, and which are contingent, whereas literature, although sometimes based on history, deals with events that could have taken place or ought to have taken place.

Aristotle thought of drama as being "an imitation of an action" and of tragedy as "falling from a higher to a lower estate" and so being removed to a less ideal situation in more tragic circumstances than before. He posited the characters in tragedy as being better than the average human being, and those of comedy as being worse.

Michael Davis, a translator and commentator of Aristotle writes:

"At first glance, mimesis seems to be a stylizing of reality in which the ordinary features of our world are brought into focus by a certain exaggeration, the relationship of the imitation to the object it imitates being something like the relationship of dancing to walking. Imitation always involves selecting something from the continuum of experience, thus giving boundaries to what really has no beginning or end. Mimêsis involves a framing of reality that announces that what is contained within the frame is not simply real. Thus the more "real" the imitation the more fraudulent it becomes."

Contrast to diegesis

It was also Plato and Aristotle who contrasted mimesis with diegesis (Greek διήγησις). Mimesis shows, rather than tells, by means of directly represented action that is enacted. Diegesis, however, is the telling of the story by a narrator; the author narrates action indirectly and describes what is in the characters' minds and emotions. The narrator may speak as a particular character or may be the invisible narrator or even the all-knowing narrator who speaks from above in the form of commenting on the action or the characters.

In Book III of his Republic (c. 373 BCE), the Ancient Greek philosopher Plato examines the style of poetry (the term includes comedy, tragedy, epic and lyric poetry): All types narrate events, he argues, but by differing means. He distinguishes between narration or report (diegesis) and imitation or representation (mimesis). Tragedy and comedy, he goes on to explain, are wholly imitative types; the dithyramb is wholly narrative; and their combination is found in epic poetry. When reporting or narrating, "the poet is speaking in his own person; he never leads us to suppose that he is any one else"; when imitating, the poet produces an "assimilation of himself to another, either by the use of voice or gesture". In dramatic texts, the poet never speaks directly; in narrative texts, the poet speaks as himself or herself.

In his Poetics, the ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle argues that kinds of poetry (the term includes drama, flute music, and lyre music for Aristotle) may be differentiated in three ways: according to their medium, according to their objects, and according to their mode or manner (section I); "For the medium being the same, and the objects the same, the poet may imitate by narration—in which case he can either take another personality as Homer does, or speak in his own person, unchanged—or he may present all his characters as living and moving before us" (section III).

Though they conceive of mimesis in quite different ways, its relation with diegesis is identical in Plato's and Aristotle's formulations; one represents, the other reports; one embodies, the other narrates; one transforms, the other indicates; one knows only a continuous present, the other looks back on a past.

In ludology, mimesis is sometimes used to refer to the self-consistency of a represented world, and the availability of in-game rationalisations for elements of the gameplay. In this context, mimesis has an associated grade: highly self-consistent worlds that provide explanations for their puzzles and game mechanics are said to display a higher degree of mimesis. This usage can be traced back to the essay "Crimes Against Mimesis" by Roger Giner-Sorolla.

Dionysian imitatio

Three centuries after Aristotle's Poetics, from 4th century BCE to 1st century BCE, the meaning of mimesis as a literary method had shifted from "imitation of nature" to "imitation of other authors." No historical record is left to explain the reason of this change, and Dionysius' work On mimesis (On imitation) got lost; most of this work contained advice on how to identify the most suitable writers to imitate and the best way to imitate them.

Latin orators and rhetoricians adopted the literary method of Dionysius' imitatio and discarded Aristotle's mimesis; the imitation literary approach is closely linked with the widespread observation that "everything has been said already," which was also stated by an Egyptian scribes around 2000 BCE. The ideal aim of this approach to literature was not originality, but to surpass the predecessor by improving their writings and set the bar to a higher level.

Samuel Taylor Coleridge

Mimesis, or imitation, as he referred to it, was a crucial concept for Samuel Taylor Coleridge's theory of the imagination. Coleridge begins his thoughts on imitation and poetry from Plato, Aristotle and Philip Sidney, adopting their concept of imitation of nature instead of other writers. His significant departure from the earlier thinkers lies in him arguing that art does not reveal a unity of essence through its ability to achieve sameness with nature. Coleridge claims:

[T]he composition of a poem is among the imitative arts; and that imitation, as opposed to copying, consists either in the interfusion of the SAME throughout the radically DIFFERENT, or the different throughout a base radically the same.

Here, Coleridge opposes imitation to copying, the latter referring to William Wordsworth's notion that poetry should duplicate nature by capturing actual speech. Coleridge instead argues that the unity of essence is revealed precisely through different materialities and media. Imitation, therefore, reveals the sameness of processes in nature.

Luce Irigaray

The French feminist Luce Irigaray used the term to describe a form of resistance where women imperfectly imitate stereotypes about themselves so as to show up these stereotypes and undermine them. This strategy is also known as strategic essentialism.

Michael Taussig

In Mimesis and Alterity (1993), the anthropologist Michael Taussig examines the way that people from one culture adopt another's nature and culture (the process of mimesis) at the same time as distancing themselves from it (the process of alterity). He describes how a legendary tribe, the "white Indians", or Cuna, have adopted in various representations figures and images reminiscent of the white people they encountered in the past (without acknowledging doing so).

Taussig, however, criticises anthropology for reducing yet another culture, that of the Cuna, for having been so impressed by their exotic (and superior) technologies of the whites, that they raised them to the status of Gods. To Taussig, this reductionism is suspect, and he argues thus from both sides in his Mimesis and Alterity to see values in the anthropologists' perspective, at the same time as defending the independence of a lived culture from anthropological reductionism. (Taussig 1993:47,48)

See also

References




Unless indicated otherwise, the text in this article is either based on Wikipedia article "Mimesis" or another language Wikipedia page thereof used under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License; or on research by Jahsonic and friends. See Art and Popular Culture's copyright notice.

Personal tools